Saturday, 4 January 2020

Liberty, Equality and Fraternity: The Ideals of the French Revolution in Krzysztof Kieslowski’s Three Colours Trilogy

This is part one of a forthcoming book called Collected Essays: Volume Two.
********************
Krzysztof Kieslowksi made a trilogy of films about the three colours of the French flag, which are called Blue (1993), White (1993) and Red (1994). These colours symbolise the values of the French Revolution – liberty, equality and fraternity. However, Kieslowski acknowledges that the trilogy’s relationship with the French revolution is oblique and that he primarily chose the subject because the funding came from France. Similarly, he made a series of films in his native Poland called The Decalogue (1989), which were loosely based on the ten commandments. This essay will not be interested in Kieslowski’s intentions, it will be interested in identifying aspects of political philosophy in these three films. It will consider political theories on liberty, equality and fraternity and it will briefly introduce theories from several influential political philosophers. It will later ascertain how these theories are represented in the three films.


Kieslowski’s earlier films had political undercurrents and they subtly criticised the communist regime in Poland, but they were chiefly concerned with more existentialist issues such as personal freedom, identity and moral choice. Indeed, Jonathan Romney writes: ‘There is something old-school existentialist about him’ (2011). Although Blue is ostensibly based on the ideals of the French revolution, Kieslowksi stressed that the film is not political: ‘We’re talking about individual freedom, a profound freedom, freedom of life’ (Romney 2011). His Polish productions were politically charged whilst his international films became more abstract. However, his Polish productions and his later international productions were about individuals who attempted to reconcile daily lives with ‘cultural myths, be they communist propaganda, Biblical proverbs or French Revolutionary slogans’ (Cummings 2003). Indeed, the trilogy is often concerned with non-political themes: ‘A nuanced and even playful approach to narrative, the paradoxes of chance, the interconnectedness of lives and a central importance given to art and performance (both public and private)’ (Cummings 2003). Kieslowski decided to make the film about the French revolution due the to the funding (Romney). However, Richard Armstrong writes: ‘[the films contain] a tension between the personal and the political’ (2007, p. 278).  However, political ideals do underpin the characters’ personal choices.
            Liberty, equality and fraternity were the ideals of the French revolution, so this essay will briefly examine its history. Inequality permeated the whole of pre-revolutionary Europe, which made revolution seem propitious. For instance, the peasantry comprised 80% of the population in France, one half of peasants owned no capital and they bore the brunt of heavy taxation (Rude 1964, p. 23). Prices rose by 30% between 1730 and 1789 and wages only increased by 22% (Rude, p. 26). Workers had no social protections and were subjected to serfdom (p. 26). However, the growth of industry soon led to an urban working class and to an industrial revolution (p. 26). Unlike the Russian revolution, it was a liberal revolution and it overturned the political and social structure of France (Droz 1967, p. 7). However, it later led to a conservative counter-revolution. Hegel was one of its main proponents and he argued that the state embodied a community which preceded and endured its individual members. Hegel thought that individuals had no substance; they were merely members of a state (Droz, p. 14). The period of 1815-1848 led to the rise of middle classes, which had prospered from the French Revolutions’ (p. 37). In keeping with the ideals of the French Revolution, the state for them was a guardian of freedom. It should not intervene in the economy or the organisation of society. Although society was riven with poverty, the role of the state was ‘negative’ (Droz, p. 45). Although the French Revolution did eventually create a middle class, it also led to a reign of terror. Robespierre became the leader of France and he believed that a more centralised state could create a more equitable society (Egan 1938, p. 27). He wanted to create a classless and co-operative society (22). He derived his ideas from Jean-Jacques Rousseau, a thinker who wrote about ‘the general will’ of the people (p. 27). Similarly, Robespierre believed that everyone should be directed to a single purpose (p. 91). Robespierre would have shuddered at the idea of an authoritarian or totalitarian state – he believed in the ideals of liberty and equality – but this is what he ended up creating (P. 89). Indeed, Egan writes that he turned from ‘a liberal humanist’ to ‘nationalist zealot’ between 1789 and1794 (p. 89). Eventually, Napoleon inherited this centralised state apparatus (Broers 1996, p. 6).  
            The philosophical foundations that opposed and supported the French Revolution were propounded in Edmund Burke’s Reflection on the Revolution in France (1790) and Thomas Paine’s The Rights of Man (1791). Burke defended the monarchy and argued that the rule of law and other customs had taken thousands of years to accomplish. It was therefore capricious to attempt to destroy it: ‘It is with infinite caution that any man ought to venture upon pulling down an edifice which has answered in any tolerable degree for ages the common purposes of society, or on building it up again, without having models or patterns’ (1790, p. 74). For a conservative, principles are established after attaining power, they do not precede it. As such, laws and political problems should respond to real problems which already exist. On the other hand, Paine argued that liberty should be extended to everyone and that we are all entitled to natural rights. He included a ‘declaration of the rights of man’ in his book, where he lists the principles of the French Revolution. These include the following principles: ‘1) Men should be free and equal in all respects. 2) All citizens should be entitled to liberty, property, security and resistance of oppression. 3) Everyone should have political liberty and should be able to do what they want as long as they do not harm others. 4) All men are free to exercise their liberty, although they are circumscribed by the law. 5) The law should only prohibit actions that harm society. 6) the law is an expression of the ‘general will’ of the community and citizens can agree or disagree with these laws. 7) The community is entitled to all honours and employment, which should be based on their skills and virtue. 8) No man should be arrested arbitrarily and they should only be arrested when they break the law 9) The law should only impose penalties that are necessary. 10) Every man should be presumed innocent before being convicted. 11) No man should be convicted because of political or religious opinions. 12) Everyone should be able to speak and think freely. 13) Policing is necessary so as to protect these rights. 14) Everyone should contribute to public expenses, but these contributions should be divided equally and based on the ability of each individual. 15) Each citizen has a right to determine how much each individual should contribute. 16) Every society requires a political constitution. 17) Everyone has a right to property and no-one should be deprived of it, unless it is of the utmost public necessity. 18) Finally, all elected representatives should be held accountable to its citizens (1791, p. 350-352). These were the central principles of the French Revolution.
            This essay will now look at political philosophies of liberty, which is broadly defined as the freedom to do certain things. It will start by looking at Issiah Berlin’s ideas on ‘positive’ and ‘negative’ liberty. ‘Negative liberty’ is defined as ‘freedom from interference’ whilst positive liberty is defined as ‘the freedom to do something’. Berlin says the following about negative liberty: ‘What is the area within the subject – a person or group of persons – should be left to do or be what he is able to do without interference from other persons?’ (1969, p. 3). On the other hand, this is how Berlin defines positive liberty: ‘What, or who, is the source of control or interference that can determine to, or be, this or that?’ (p. 3). According to negative liberty, an individual is free when no-one interferes in his activity (p.3). An individual is unfree when he is prevented from doing something. There are external societal factors that prevent freedom, such as poverty (p. 4). Berlin also says that mental and physical incapacities also prevent freedom. Berlin: ‘The wider the area of non-interference, the wider my freedom’ (p. 4). According to Berlin, social harmony and equality can only be achieved by bestowing a private life to individuals. Crucially, neither the state nor any other entity should intervene in the private realm (p. 6). On the other hand, positive liberty aims to provide resources which make individuals free. Liberty means that the individual wants to be a ‘master’ of his own destiny. An individual is ‘a subject, not an object’ and he is ‘moved by reasons, conscious purposes, which are my own’ (p. 8). However, Berlin admits that coercing an individual in the name of a higher goal can sometimes be justified. These include causes such as public health, social justice, the fight against fascism, etc. (p. 9). However, Berlin points out that definitions of what is good and just vary drastically amongst individuals (p. 9). In some cases, however, coercion in the name of the common good might enlarge one’s own liberty (p. 9). The Second World War is a good example of this, as many people argued that the fight against fascism was an attempt to protect individual freedom.
            However, some liberals wanted to create ‘an enabler state.’ Social liberals, as opposed to ‘classical liberals,’ wanted to create state resources that intervened in the economy and combated poverty. They did this because they wanted to heighten, not diminish, individual freedom. William Beveridge provided the intellectual formulation of ‘welfare state’ in his ‘Beveridge report.’ On the other hand, classical liberals argue that state resources create dependency and that they intrude into the private lives of individuals. Social liberals, meanwhile, argue that they empower the individual by providing him with resources such as money, health and education. It enriches their autonomy, as opposed to creating dependency. Supporters of positive liberty believe that a degree of wealth redistribution enriches individual liberty (Sloman 2015). Martha Nussbaum, a social liberal, views negative liberty ‘as an incoherent idea,’ as all our choices are either permitted or inhibited by others. All choices depend on resources such as education, health, food, etc. The state should provide resources such as education, health and redistributive welfare and they develop the capacities of the individual (Nussbaum 2011, p. 65).
             However, as this essay identified, Kieslowski was mainly interested in personal, not political, freedom. Robert J. Havinghurst writes about the individualism of the west and contrasts it with the ‘groupism’ of the east. In line with Berlin’s ideas, he writes that freedom involves the absence of constraint and the freedom to speak or assemble (1952, p. 230). However, Havinghurst writes that excessive individualism can lead to loneliness and isolation. As such, people need some sense of belonging, such as nationhood and family. Western societies are more individualistic, and have less encroachment from the state, than the communistic east (p. 235). These societies emphasise personal freedom. On the other hand, several political philosophers have argued that political freedom is more important than personal freedom. Hannah Arendt did this in her book On Revolution (1963), where she emphasised participatory democracy and self-government. Freedom, for her, was public; that is, ‘it was a network of relation between human beings' (Wellmer 1999, p. 84). In a liberal democracy, the state must recognise that each individual is an end in itself, has equal value and that he has a right to choose the life that he wants to lead. Moral rights and values emerge from our intrinsic humanity, not political institutions (Wellmer, p. 91). In private, however, the individual is free to choose what to do without interference from the state (p. 91). In the public sphere, however, members of the community are equal and they have the power to influence decisions (p. 91). Hence, Arendt placed more emphasis on political freedom whilst Issiah Berlin thought that personal freedom was more important (p. 94). Although Arendt shared some concern for a liberal conception of rights, she thought that it was a necessary precondition for political freedom, which involved ‘self-government based on common action and shared deliberation’ (Dybikowski 1981, 208).
            This essay will now ascertain how these ideas are represented in the film. Julie is played by Julliette Binoche and she talks to a lawyer in one scene. She is framed via a mid-shot and the values of liberty are reinforced by the blue wallpaper and the saturation. The lawyer is framed via a mid-shot. Julie tells him: ‘You’ll take care of mother. No-one must know. The money will go to the same account.’ Julie is on the left side of the mid-shot and the entire room is covered in blue wallpaper. The lawyer says: ‘May I ask you why?’ The mid-shot tilts down and reveals Julie holding blue wrapping and this once more reifies the underlying value of liberty. She says: ‘No.’ The lighting, the saturation and the mise-en-scene allude to the revolutionary ideal of freedom. Most viewers, however, would be aware of this, as the title of the trilogy patently alludes to it. The scene also references ideas on positive and negative liberty, as Julie wants no interference from others so that she can be free to pursue her own freedom. She is not prevented from doing this and, in that sense, her liberty is negative. The state does not tell her how to lead her life, she is an end in herself and she chooses how to act. Political intuitions do not determine her choices and she makes her own choices. She also cuts herself off from family and friends and she wants no interference from either them or the state. By contrast, positive liberty interferes in society so as to enhance the choices that people make. In this particular scene, Julie relies on a lawyer to take care of her accounts. As such, she still relies on other individuals and institutions that either permit or inhibit her choices. Later on, she relies on a landlord to rent an apartment and on utility companies for electricity, gas, etc. Nussbaum claims that negative liberty is an incoherent idea, as all individual choices are dependent on resources which are controlled by others. However, Julie is still free to pursue the life that she individually wants to lead.

            Oliver is a family acquaintance and a composer. This essay will analyse a scene where Julie cuts herself off from him and it will bear in mind ideas on negative and positive liberty. The scene starts with a mid-shot. Oliver stands on the far right of the screen and it is dark outside. Once more, the screen is saturated with the colour blue, which reinforces themes of political liberty. There is more light on Oliver side of the frame, but the rest of the frame is enveloped in darkness. The sound design is comprised of the sound of rain. The camera work edits to a mid-shot of Julie, who is on the left side of the frame and it later tilts up to reveal Oliver. The mise-en-scene is once more comprised of blue wallpaper and the sky is tinged with blue. The camera work edits to a close-up shot of Julie and Oliver kissing. The camera work soon edits to reveal a mid-shot Oliver sleeping, where there is a lot of contrast between dark and light. Julie is placed on the left side of the screen whilst Oliver lies on the right side of the frame. This mid-shot is followed by a close-up and the framing of the bodies emphasises their distance from each other. The camera work edits to a close-up shot of Julie smiling, where she is surrounded by a blue backdrop. She says: ‘I appreciate what you did for me. Now you see, I’m like any other woman. I sweat, I cough, I have cavities. You won’t miss me. You understand that now.’ The camera work edits to a close-up shot of Oliver who looks bemused. The mid-shot creates a sense of union between the two characters whilst the close-us create a sense of distance. This is followed by a low-angle mid-shot of Julie walking away and we see it from Oliver’s perspective. Julie’s liberty is negative, as she is cutting herself off from others. However, there is nothing political in this scene because it is about personal relations. However, in other scenes Julie does rely on political institutions to extricate herself from others. On the other hand, this scene deals with her private life, where she cuts off contact with a close relation. She does this so as to focus on her personal freedom, where she is free to do what she wants to do. She is free to pursue whatever she wants to do in her private life and she is unencumbered by responsibilities or the kind of ‘common action’ that Arendt prescribed.
            These two scenes demonstrate how Julie tries to cut off herself off from others. In other words, it shows how she exercises her ‘negative liberty’ and personal freedom. Kieslowski claims that he was more interested in personal freedom, but there is one scene where she connects to a higher political ideal. Her husband composed a piece about the ideals of the European Union and she attempts to complete it after he passes away. The piece is about values which transcend national borders, it is internationalist and it is about values which a community of nations adhere to. These values are higher than the self and the personal relations which the rest of the film deals with. Indeed, Julie starts to reconnect with society and with others once she starts writing the piece. The scene starts with a mid-shot of a television set in a night club and it is followed with a 125-degree close-up of Julie. The TV program is once more saturated by blue and the set design is blue. Oliver says: ‘The concerto will be played by twelve symphonic orchestras in the twelve united European cities.’ The camera, framed via a close-up, pans across the score. This was during the early 90s, following the demise of communism and the so-called ‘end of history.’ The ideals of this piece are higher than the ideals of the nation state, they are about ideals which transcend borders. A later scene depicts Julie and Oliver working on the score together and it starts with a mid-shot of Oliver’s apartment. This is followed with an extreme close-up of the score, which pans across the piece as the score plays in the background. The camera blurs out of focus, so that the music comes to the fore. The editing later alternates between mid-shots of Julie and Oliver and they are framed via 125 or 175 angles. In these scenes, Julie reconnects with higher political ideals of the ideals and she also reconnects with intimate personal relations, as she becomes Oliver’s partner. The film recreates this with mid-shots of Julie and Olivier, which conveys their close personal relationship. It conveys the connection with political ideals via extreme close-ups of the score, the soundtrack of the score and the blue tinge on the screen.
            This essay has examined the ideals of freedom in Blue and it will now examine the ideals of equality in White, which is also a multifarious term. The broad meaning is that people should be treated the same way and that no-one should be entitled to unfair privileges. Commentators talk about ‘freedom to what’ and ‘equality of what,’ as both terms have different meanings. This essay has already examined positive, negative, personal and political freedom. It will now examine the equal worth of individuals, equality of outcome and opportunity, the ideas of John Rawls and the ideas of R. H. Tawney. Richard Arneson defines egalitarianism as the belief that people should be treated the same way and that everyone is of equal worth (2013). Meanwhile, Nicholas Kirby makes a distinction between equal worth and equal authority. Equal worth is the belief that each individual is of each worth whilst equal authority is the belief that no individual should be under the natural authority of anyone else (2018, p. 297). Equal worth was originally based on the idea that what is good for the individual and society would lead to redemption in heaven. After Christianity, Jeremy Bentham argued that individual happiness was considered good if the lower rungs of society were as equally happy as the higher ones (p. 303). Meanwhile, unequal authority involves differences in race, sex, class, education, prosperity, age, virtues, talents, etc. (p. 303). Kirby writes that individuals have equal rights and that everyone should be able to make laws through the ballot box and consensual decision making (p. 304). Each individual has authority over himself and the ability to determine his own decisions, but no individual should have authority over another individual (p. 304). The democratic conception of society views individuals as equal members/citizens of a community (p. 305), which has led to certain kinds of liberals warning about ‘the tyranny of the majority’ (p. 305). Over time, however, societies have diversified, which has incorporated a multiplicity of values. As time passes, the individual has less in common with the majority and we start to speak less of a communal self (p. 305). According to Rosseau, the government is a body which rules everyone, but the continues to have the authority to rule himself. When the government enforces its rules over the individual, it forces him to obey his previous exercise of authority (p. 308). Kant, meanwhile, claims that laws are given to the individual, but these laws are universal and they are commensurable with his autonomous choices (p. 308).
            This essay will analyse a scene of a court scene in White and it will look at these ideas on equal worth and equal authority. In a democratic society, all individuals are equal under the rule of law. Everyone is of equal worth and the law should not discriminate on the grounds of race, class or gender. The law should be ‘the servant’ of its people, not its ‘master.’ This scene starts with a long shot in the right-hand corner of the building, where several lawyers walk around. The building is brightly luminated. The lawyers wear black and they walk on top of the patterned white floor. All of the lawyers are in a higher position in society, although everyone is equal under the rule of law. The film edits to a court room and it starts with a low angle mid-shot in the left-hand corner of the room. This is followed with a high angle long-shot of the courtroom in the centre of the room. The judge is in the middle, Karol is on the left and his wife Dominique is on the right. The film later edits to close-ups of both Karol and Dominique. At this point, Karol says: ‘Where’s my equality? Is not speaking French a reason for the court to refuse to hear my case?’ The judge says: ‘What is it you want?’ Karol: ‘I need time to save my marriage.’ This is followed with close-ups of Karol and Dominque. Karol does not feel that the law is treating him as an equal, as he cannot speak French and he speaks through an interpreter. He feels that the law is not being just, as it is treating him unequally because of his nationality. According to Kant, the law should be universal and follow universal laws of justice, morality, etc. Nationhood should not be brought to the fore, as the law should be universal and should be applied equally to people from different cultures. The law in this scene is not really being the servant of the individual, either. He has been deprived of some freedom and someone else decide his own fate. Karol is not really of equal worth, since he struggles to communicate and he has no financial security following his divorce. The alternating close-ups of Karol and Dominique emphasises their position in society whilst the long-shot of the judge emphasises his loftiness.      
            This essay will now distinguish between equality of outcome and equality of opportunity. Equality of outcome attempts to equalise what people become rather than where they begin, which is what equality of opportunity tries to do (Phillips 2004, p. 1). Equality of outcome attempts to equalise resources, but people argue that this ignores the diversity of societies, as people’s preferences vary enormously (p. 1). As such, the division of resources leaves either an excess or scarcity of what different people consider either valuable or worthless (p. 1). This is sometimes called the politics of envy, as ‘it attacks achievements that stray above the norm’ (p. 2). On the other hand, the opposite argument claims that people should not expect to have the same amount of happiness, misery or commodities, but they can expect to have the same opportunities to thrive (p. 2). Phillips: ‘[It is important to distinguish between] inequalities that arise from circumstances beyond our own control and those legitimate ones that arise from the exercise of personal choice’ (p. 2). Ronald Dworkin writes that the obsession with income redistribution overlooks the choices that people make with the resources which are available to them (p. 3). As such, any redistribution of resources should take into account the decisions that people make with their lives (p. 3). It is odd to insist that everyone should do the same thing with their time. However, equalising income would make more sense, as it would enable individuals to do what they want with their money, which equalise starting points, not outcomes (p. 4). However, given differences in preferences it is also odd to say that everyone should devote their time to accumulating money (p. 4). As such, resources matter more than incomes. If you lack resources to do things, you will not be able to do anything. For instance, a disabled person needs a wheelchair to move (p. 5). For this reason, Phillips argues that welfare focuses too much on differences between income rather than on individuals as autonomous beings. Public resources such as education, health, etc. should empower them to choose to lead the lives that they individually want to lead (p. 6). Additionally, equality of opportunity takes into account ‘bad luck’ arguments, such as being born with a physical or mental condition or being born into poverty (p. 2).
            ‘Equality of outcome’ has been to some degree attempted in the western world, when governments redistribute wealth through progressive tax rates. Indeed, one of the main objectives of European social democratic parties is to create a more equitable distribution of income (Kastning 2013). However, equality of outcome has been more assiduously implemented in the Soviet Union, as communism aimed to level income distribution completely. However, the abolition of private property did not lead to the elimination of classes or inequality (Schwartz and Pease 1973, p. 141). Although the French and American revolutions were interested in equality, the Russian and Chinese revolutions aimed to create classless societies, but classes continued to exist (p. 141). The first period of the Soviet Union aimed to create radical levelling, but the second period led ‘to a more differentiated status system’ (p. 142). Lenin’s first period levelled incomes drastically, but this was relaxed during the New Economic Policy. The most ambitious attempt at levelling involved the collectivisation of agriculture and the persecution of the Kulaks. After this third period, the distribution of income became more pronounced because income tax laws ended up favouring the highest paid members of society (p. 142). Contrary to the communistic ethos, this led to a greater income differential between ‘manual’ and ‘mental’ workers (p. 144). Additionally, the communists were disdainful towards leisure activities and tended to prioritise activities which were socially useful (p. 149).
            Kieslowski released White two years after the dissolution of the Soviet Union. Although people talked about ‘the end of history,’ and about exporting social and economic liberalism to the east, the transition to capitalism and liberal democracy faltered. Boris Yeltsin lifted price controls, prices returned to normal levels and inflation soared to 1,000% in 1992 (Steele 2007). The government sold off state assets and created a class of oligarchic billionaires (Steele). Indeed, White deals with this, as the protagonist makes millions through the black market. One scene depicts him prying on a conversation and he discovers that two people plan to buy a plot of state-owned land and build warehouses. The scene starts with a close-up of a man talking; the camera is placed at the back of the car and framed via a 70-degree angle. This is followed with a 180 degree shot of Karol feigning sleep. One of them says: ‘But if we triple the investment… that’d be very smart.’ The sky is grey and the car is white, which reinforces the values of equality. The scene starts with a mid-shot of the car driving up the hill, but it soon edits to a 270 degree angle of a close-up shot of the man in the car. There is a 180 degree angle mid-shot, from Karol’s perspective, of the two men talking. The camera pans to the left and follows their movements. They talk about a ‘30% profit.’ This is followed with a 180 degree mid-shot of Karol prying on the conversation. The camera angles are often subjective and from the point of view of Karol. The decision to film on location reifies the values of equality, as they are surrounded by snowy and a wintery climate. Karol was born into the lower rungs of communist Poland, where class inequalities continued to exist. This is why he moves to Paris, but he is still treated badly. However, he becomes wealthy through sheer luck, which might emphasise the arbitrary nature of capitalistic equality of opportunity. The distribution of wealth after the dissolution of the Soviet Union was undemocratic, as people gained economic power by just being at the right place at the right time, which is both undemocratic and unmeritocratic. The ideals of socialism call for the democratisation of the economy and for the community to share property and wealth. However, this was taken to another extreme with Boris Yeltsin, as individuals gained large state monopolies and this was not even based on notions of democracy or merit. Communism did not produce complete equality of outcome either, as manual workers like Karol remained in the lower rungs of society and they did not have opportunities to mobilise upwards. Ironically, the free-for-all capitalism in this case does offer these opportunities.


            This essay will now examine John Rawls’ ideas on equality. John Rawls wrote an influential book called A Theory of Justice (1971), where he tried to reach a reach a compromise between liberty and equality. He starts the book with a hypothetical ‘veil of ignorance,’ a society of amnesiacs who are in need of a political constitution. Rawls comes up with ‘two principles of justice’ for such a society:
1)     Each person has an equal claim to a fully adequate scheme of equal basic rights and liberties, which scheme is compatible with the same scheme for all; and this scheme the equal political liberties, and only these liberties, are to be guaranteed their fair value.
2)     Social and economic inequalities are to satisfy two conditions: a) they are to be attached to positions and offices open to all conditions of fair equality of opportunity and b) they are to be to the greatest benefit of the least disadvantaged members of the society’ (1971, p. 5-6).
The first principle emphasises liberal rights whilst the second principle emphasises egalitarianism, but Rawls also argued that liberal rights were in themselves a form of social justice (Rawls, p. 197-98) However, number of criticisms have been made about the theory. These criticisms have been made by leftists, other liberals, libertarians, conservatives and communitarians. Some egalitarians believe that the theory underestimates the importance of equality. G. A. Cohen points out that some work is less fulfilling than other work and that people in the lower rungs of society might have to undertake work that is unpleasant and dangerous. Additionally, other leftists believe that people being better off than others results in them having more power. Rawls argues that the ‘difference principle’ is permitted as long as it leads to basic political liberties. However, vast differences in wealth make it impossible for poor people to be elected to political office or to even have their political views represented. Meanwhile, utilitarians argue that the theory does not maximise utility. Libertarians, or ‘classical liberals,’ argue that the theory infringes on property rights. The second principle requires redistributive taxation for the benefit of the poor and theorists like Robert Nozick think that this involves the immoral takings of just holdings. Some go as far as arguing that this taxation is a form of theft. The ‘desert-based principle’ argues that some people deserve their just takings for hard work. These people come to their advantaged position because of their hard work and their position in society is thus fair. Finally, ‘luck egalitarianism’ argues that inequalities are only just when they are derived from the choices that people make and that the individual is responsible for (Lamont and Favor 2017). Finally, the communitarian critique of Rawls argues that ideas of justice and fairness are derived from society rather than the self (Mansfield 1990, p. 18). The veil of ignorance assumes that people are individuals without any social ties. According to a communitarian view, a political constitution should take into account shared values as well as liberal rights (Mansfield, p. 17).
            This essay will now hold these theories in mind whilst analysing scenes in White. Karol ends up with no financial security when he breaks up with his former wife. As such, inequality in this case does not protect the least vulnerable in society. The scene starts with a mid-shot of Karol in front of a cash machine. It is late at night and the street is dark and the sound is recorded on location. The camera tilts down and dollies into a close-up of the cash machine, from a 180 degree angle. The machine says that his money has been confiscated. The film later edits to a scene in a bank and Karol is framed via a low angle shot. The bank clerk says: ‘Your account is frozen. Your account cannot be used, it’s invalidated. […] I can’t give it to you.’ He proceeds to cut the card. We later see a mid-shot, shot on location, of Karol in the streets of Paris, where he is cold and uncomfortable. We later see a low-angle close-up of Karol busking at the metro, where he encounters another Polish individual. We The Polish individual is framed via a low-angle mid-shot; that is, from Karol’s perspective. The man offers to smuggle him back to Poland. The low-angle mid-shots, which sometimes tilt, are often subjective. They often recreate his lowly position, as he is often on the floor begging for money. In these scenes, inequality is not justified from a Rawlsian perspective, as it does not satisfy the needs of the least disadvantaged members of society. Karol has not chosen to end up in his predicament; it happens due to forces beyond his control. He did not choose to divorce, nor to have his card cancelled. The egalitarian critique of Rawls argues that differences in wealth result in a small minority having enormous power over the disenfranchised. Karol is a foreign labourer who ends up homeless and he is represented by politicians or trade unions. Meanwhile, libertarians do not believe that Karol is entitled to a redistributive safety net, as it invades their just holdings, even though Karol is homeless through no fault of his own. Communitarians argue that Rawls sees individuals as atoms who are devoid of social ties. However, Rawls would think that Karol is entitled to rights which are denied to him, such as unemployment insurance. However, Karol does have opportunities to mobilise. Under communism, he remains stranded in the same economic class. The opportunities that he encounters, though, are very sinister. Someone offers to kill him for money and he eventually makes millions through the black market. As such, some opportunities in the capitalistic system are sinister, immoral and criminal.   

            This essay will now examine R. H. Tawney, a British socialist political theorist. Tawney wrote about equality in books such as Equality (1931) and The Acquisitive Society (1920). Tawney argued that poverty was a symptom and consequence of a disorder in social values. Capitalism stressed individual rights without any reference to the function that society plays in forming the individual (Foote 1985, p. 74). Tawney thought that the decline of religion led to an emphasis on rights without any social purpose (p. 24). Capitalism did not serve the community, it was only interested in individual self-interest (p. 75). Under capitalism, people use their skills and energy without any reference to morality. People are used as a means to self-advancement (p. 75). The brotherhood of man and moral principles become irrelevant and people only become interested in material gain (p. 75). Tawney wanted society to be based on duties, obligations, unity and cooperation rather than division and mutual antagonism (p. 75). In his book Equality, Tawney argued that, although the upper classes denounced class struggle, they practised it all the time. As such, they endorsed vast differences in income, security, culture and health (p. 76). Tawney thought that the redistribution of wealth was insufficient; he also wanted society to value our common humanity (p. 76). Economic power was concentrated in one class and Tawney wanted to tackle this by breaking down ‘rigid divisions between labour and management’ (p. 77). Lower income workers were equally entitled to better wages and for their right to organise themselves efficiently. As such, they were equally entitled to have a say in the management process (p. 77). Inequality in health and education led to ill-health, incapacity and high infant mortality. These inequalities were concentrated in working class areas and they were hereditary. Their class background condemned them to overcrowded classrooms, poor facilities, poor housing and poor medical care. Social traditions pampered a few children and deprived the rest (p. 77). Both educational privilege and capitalism segregated people into classes (p. 78). As such, Tawney proposed a free health service, more state control of public education, better equipped schools and better-quality education. A small segment of society enjoyed liberty whilst the majority were restricted to unfreedom (p. 78). Tawney defined freedom as the ability to act positively for the community. Additionally, Tawney argued that freedom for everyone also entails an acceptance of social rules so as to prevent the abuse of power (p. 78).
            Karol’s homelessness can also be analysed from a Tawneyian perspective. Tawney would argue that Karol’s homelessness is a symptom of an uncaring society. Capitalism does not meet the needs of people because it is self-interested and profit-driven. This comes through most strongly in the scene where the clerk cuts up his credit card. He is not interested in the welfare of the customer; he is simply interested in the workings of capitalism and he shows no compunction. Tawney would argue that Karol ends up homeless due to the failings of society, not due to his own fault. Christianity was interested in catering for the welfare of everyone, but the acquisitive society is only concerned with profit and not with meeting the needs of people. Enormous inequalities in wealth and income mean that power and wealth are concentrated in a single class. Workers have no say in the economy, as Karol is not allowed to express himself. Management control the economy and workers like Karol are not allowed to have any say on their desperate situation. Educational privilege also segregates people into classes, as Karol is consigned to his lowly class.
            However, Karol eventually rises from his situation by abusing power. This is contrary to what Tawney wanted, as he wanted liberty to respect social rules. He turns to the black market, swindles his wife, orchestrates his own death, frames his wife and sends her to prison. Although he is initially consigned to unfreedom, he abuses its rules once he acquires liberty of action and economic power. There are scenes in the film which show him framing his own death. This scene starts with a 90 degree mid-shot of Karol’s friend, followed by a 180 degree mid shot of the executor of his will. The editing alternates between these two shots. This is followed with an extreme close-up of Karol’s passport being shredded. A later scene depicts Karol choosing his own grave and Karol later blames his ex-wife for his murder. Earlier on, Karol is not protected from destitution by any safety net. However, he acquires his wealth by abusing the system and he keeps acting in a self-interested way. According to Tawney, a Christian society would prevent him from falling into poverty, but Karol rises from his lowly social class by abusing social rules.
            This essay will now look at the final ideal, fraternity. Fraternity has been defined as the ideal of brotherhood, friendship, community or co-operation (Ashtana 1992, p.118). Fraternity is the view ‘that we are brothers’ and that we are on an equal footing’ (Denman 1995, p. 193). Aristotle initially argued that friendship is an important aspect of both politics and justice (Asthana, p. 118). Indeed, some people argue that politics is a social contract between citizens (p. 118). In the medieval ages, people emphasised the political value of friendship and that we are all the sons of God and, hence, brothers (p. 119). Meanwhile, the French revolution emphasised neither the Aristotelean meaning nor the meaning of the French revolution (p. 119), it was a springboard to political action (p. 119). The majority were exploited, poor and hungry. Hence, everyone had to unite in fraternal friendships so as to overcome class divisions and national boundaries (p. 119). Hegel went as far as seeing the state as the expression of the collective human spirit. Meanwhile, Marx wanted the toiling masses to unite as a fraternal class so as to overcome exploitation (p. 121). Meanwhile, liberals accept communities as long as they are consistent with the autonomy of the individual (p. 123). Above all else, there is a democratic need for fraternity because ‘it provides the context within which equality can be established and freedom can be protected’ (P. 123). In other words, it is a means through which to achieve the ideals of freedom and equality. Additionally, fraternal values are also biologically important. Evolutionary biology rewards altruistic behaviour, as organisms help each other to survive this way. Evolution does not reward selfish behaviour, as it does not lead to reproductive fitness (Okasha 2003).
            The Soviet Union assiduously enforced the ideal of equality, but they also assiduously enforced ideals of fraternity. Indeed, solidarity is a central component of socialism. The Polish philosopher Lesek Kolakowski wrote about ‘enforced fraternity’ in the USSR. Indeed, British conservative philosopher Roger Scruton writes about him in glowing terms. Churchill argued that democracy is the least worst system and Kolakowski argued that the same is true for capitalism (Scruton 2009). Capitalism emerged organically after the spread of commerce. No-one planned it and it did not need an all-embracing ideology. Socialism was an ideological construction, but capitalism was merely human nature at work. Scruton quotes Kolakowski thusly:

Socialism is an attempt to institutionalize and enforce fraternity. It seems obvious by now that a society in which greed is the main motivation of human action, for all of its repugnant and deplorable aspects, is incomparably better than a society based on compulsory brotherhood, whether in national or international socialism (Scruton 2009).
Meanwhile, the democratic socialist Nathan J. Robinson also quotes Kolakowski in his own publication Current Affairs. In this quote, Kolakowski still argues that it is important to preserve the importance of fraternity.
 [It would be] a pity if the collapse of communist socialism resulted in the demise of the socialist tradition as a whole and the triumph of Social Darwinism as the dominant ideology. Fraternity under compulsion is the most malignant idea devised in modern times. This is no reason, however, to scrap the idea of human fraternity. If it is not something that can be effectively achieved by means of social engineering, it is useful as a statement of goals. The socialist idea is dead as a project for an alternative society. But as a statement of solidarity with the underdog and the oppressed, as a motivation to oppose Social Darwinism, as a light that keeps before our eyes something higher than competition and greedfor all these reasons, socialismthe ideal, not the systemstill has its uses. (Robinson 2018)
Indeed, many European socialist parties talk about the importance of socialism as an ideal rather than as an alternative economic system (Kastning 2013). If fraternity is to be of any importance, it should be realised by autonomous individuals and through voluntary associations. Scruton believes that institutions and human relationships are important, but they should come about organically and through private associations.
            Martha Nussbaum writes about the tension between solitude and fraternity in her book The Fragility of Goodness: Luck and Ethics in Greek Tragedy and Philosophy (1986). Nussbaum argues that, although self-sufficiency, solitude and contemplation is enriching and important, it still needs some sort of external stimulation to instigate it (p. 343). Political citizenship, political attachment, personal love and personal friendship are also important values (p. 343). Indeed, Aristotle argues that social, political relations are essential parts of the good life (p. 344). Other hermetical thinkers from antiquity, such as Epicurus and Phyrro, urged contemplative detachment from civic life (p. 345). Aristotle argues that membership of a political community is in itself good for developing character (p. 345). This is because laws, political institutions and public education nurture individual lives (p. 346). Aristotle argued that a public education would create a sense of belonging to the city and the community (p. 347). It requires ‘support from without’ (p. 347). The good life is still dependent on individual choice; slaves cannot choose and are therefore not fully human (p. 348). Although Aristotle values individual choice and autonomy, political life is part of our nature. The Cyclopes in Homer’s Odyssey are not fully human, as they have no social or political life. Aristotle believes that virtue is ‘relational’ and that justice, courage, moderation and generosity are impossible without it (p. 352). By increasing our activity in the world, we make it meet our demands (p. 352). The city, however, is a plurality of free and equal citizens who make their own choices (p. 352). Aristotle defends family bonds, but he also defends personal separateness. Plato wants to eliminate the family and private property, but Aristotle believes that diversity enriches society whereas Plato’s view ‘impoverishes the world’ (p. 353).
              Red is based on the ideal of fraternity. The main character, played by Irene Jacob, meets a reclusive judge. The former judge pries on private telephone conversations. The character initially meets the judge, played by Jean Trignitant, because she runs over his dog. The scene starts with a mid-shot Trignitant and Jacob. This is followed with a low-angle 90 degree mid-shot, with light coming in from outside. Jacob tells Trignitant: ‘Don’t do this anymore.’ Trignitant says: ‘I’ve done it all of my life.’ ‘What were you? A cop’ ‘Worse. A judge.’ The editing alternates between 90 degree close ups of Jacob and Trignitant. A mid-shot of Jacob tilts down as Trignitant leans down. Jacob later says: ‘Everyone deserves a private life.’ The room is filled with many books and this reveals that he is very learned. The camera angles are often framed via mid-shots, which reveal the vastness of the house and how it is festooned with books and other objects. The vastness of the house, and the framing, emphasise how lonely the judge is and how he has cut himself off from fraternal bonds. There is also a small statue of dogs, which reveal his affection for the animal. Trignitant encourages Jacob to confront the family about his illicit activities, but she rescinds because she does not want to break the family apart. This has parallels with Nussbaum’s ideas on justice, as the attempt to act ethically has to take into consideration factors which are outside the control of the individual and which could potentially bring ruin. Jacob also wants the judge to respect the autonomy and personal separateness of the family, but she feels that Trignitant is encroaching on their own autonomy so as to pursue egotistical choices. Jacob would also be trampling on their fraternal bonds, as breaking the family apart would break apart the ties that hold them together.

            However, Irene Jacob and the judge become closer. There is a scene wherey meet at a venue with red seats, red wallpaper and a red podium. We see a mid-shot of Jacob and the judge who are both far away from each other, but they are both pleased to be near each other. We later see a long shot of the theatre and the red seats. There is a mid-shot of Jacob and Trigninant is in the lower right hand corner of the frame. ‘You came. You knew the invitation came from me? ‘I’d hoped so.’ Trignitant later says: ‘I’m leaving tomorrow. I came to say goodbye.’ The camera work later edits to mid-shots from the characters’ perspectives. Trignitant says: ‘You’re the woman I never met.’ The abundance of red obviously emphasises the values of fraternity. Also, the camera work emphasises the distance from each other, but the framing of the bodies via close-ups brings them closer together. Fraternity was championed during the French Revolution because it overcame divisions between classes and people. In this case, both characters overcome their divisions and bonds, even though they are different from each other. Fraternity was also a means towards the ideals of freedom and equality, as common unity created the conditions that could eradicate inequalities in class, wealth, gender, etc. They also overcome their divisions so that they can pursue their own individual freedom. Indeed, fraternity in this case is reached voluntarily. This is line with Nussbaum’s and Aristotle’s views on fraternity, as they wanted a diverse political body to unite of their own volition. It also in line with Kolakowski’s views on fraternity, as they are behaviour has not been enforced. It is done by autonomous individuals, not an arbitrary centrally planned hierarchy. Kolakowksi preferred the most egotistical form of unregulated capitalism to this other sinister outcome.
            The French revolution emerged after a period of extreme inequality and its ideals were delineated by Thomas Paine in The Rights of Man. This essay looked at positive liberty, negative liberty, personal freedom and political freedom. Negative liberty emphasises absence of interference whilst positive liberty aims to interfere and provide resources which strengthen individual freedom. The character in the film, Julie, tries to cut herself off from others, but she still depends on resources and institutions to achieve this. This essay looked at both personal and political freedom. Julie strives after personal freedom, but she later connects to a higher political ideal when she writes a piece of music dedicated to the European Union. This essay examined several aspects of equality, namely the equal worth of individuals, the differences between equality of opportunity and equality of outcome, the ideas of John Rawls and the ideas of R. H. Tawney. The Polish character Karol does not believe that he is treated equally at a trial, as he does not speak French. In a democracy, however, laws should be universal and all people should have equal worth. The differences between equality of opportunity and equality in outcome are crucial in White, as the protagonist makes a fortune after the collapse of communism. The communist countries attempted to level incomes completely, but this meant that individuals in the lower rungs rarely mobilised upwards. There is more equality of opportunity in the capitalist west, but Karol makes his fortune by abusing the system. This essay looked at the ideas of John Rawls, who argued that a decent society should let its citizens enjoy basic liberties. He also argued that inequalities should only be permitted if they benefit the least advantaged members of society. Inequalities do not benefit Karol in White, as he has no financial security following his divorce and the safety net does not prevent him from becoming homeless. According to R. H. Tawney, capitalism was based on individual self-interest and it was immoral. According to Tawney’s view, Karol ends up homeless due to the uncaring nature of the capitalist society. Finally, Red deals with fraternity. The character played by Irene Jacob bonds with a character played by Trignitant, although she initially objects to him prying on the conversation of his neighbours. Their fraternal bonding overcomes their divisions and this is how the French Revolution conceived of fraternity. They do this, however, of their own volition, which is in line with the ideas of Aristotle. Aristotle wanted a society that valued common citizenship and friendship, but he still wanted it to be comprised of plurality and individual choice. Similarly, Lesek Kolakowski argued that compulsory fraternity was ‘malignant’ and that he preferred a highly unregulated and immoral society to ‘compulsory fraternity.’ However, he still thought that it was important to value fraternity as long as it respected human agency. This is what happens in Red, as the characters bond of their own volition. These are the aspects of liberty, equality and fraternity that this essay has identified in these three films.

Works Cited
Arneson, Richard. (2013) ‘Egalitarianism.’ The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Available from: https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/egalitarianism/
Armstrong, Richard. (2007)Krzysztof Kieslowski.’ In The Rough Guide to Film. London: Penguin.
Asthana, Mukul. (1992) ‘Fraternity: A Political Ideal.’ In The Indian Journal of Political Science. Vol. 53, No. 1.  
            Berlin, Issiah. (1969) ‘Two Concepts of Liberty’ In Four Essays on Liberty. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Broers, Michael. (1996) Europe Under Napoleon: 1799-1815. London: Hodders Education.
Burke, Edmund. (1973) Originally published in 1790. Reflections on the Revolution in France. New York: Anchor Books.
            Cummings, Doug. (2003) ‘Great Directors: Kieslowski, Krzysztof.’ Senses of Cinema. Available from: http://sensesofcinema.com/2003/great-directors/kieslowski/
Denes, Iván Roltan. (2008) ‘Personal Liberty and Political Freedom: Four Interpretations.’ In European Journal of Political Theory. Vol. 7, No. 1.
Denman, Kamilla. (1995) ‘Recovering FraternitĂ© in the Works of Rousseau: Jean-Jacques’ Lost Brother.’ In Eighteenth-Century Studies. Vol. 29, No. 2.
Droz, Jacques. (1967) Europe Between Revolutions: 1815-1848. London: Harper Collins.
Dybikowski, James. (1981) ‘Civil Liberty.’ In American Philosophy Quarterly. Vol. 18, No. 4.
Egan, Michael. (1938) Robespierre: Nationalist Dictator. New York: Columbia University Press.
Foote, Geoffrey. (1985) The Labour Party’s Political Thought: A History. London: Croom Helm.
Havighurst, Robert J. (1952) ‘Personal Freedom: Its Meaning for International Understanding.’ In Bulletin of the American Association of Professors. Vol. 38, No. 2.
Kastning, Thomas. (2013) Basics on Social Democracy. Bonn: Friedrich-Ebert-Stiftung.
Kirby, Nicholas. (2018) ‘Two Concepts of Basic Equality.’ In Res Publica.  Vol. 24.
Lamon, Julian and Favor, Christi. (2017) ‘Distributive Justice.’ The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Available from: https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/justice-distributive/
Mansfield, Jonathan Edward. (1990) John Rawls, The Concept of a Liberal Self, and the Communitarian Critique. Dissertations and Theses. Portland State University. Paper 4142.
Nussbaum, Martha. (1986) The Fragility of Goodness: Luck and Ethics in Greek Tragedy and Philosophy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
.Nussbaum, Martha. (2011) Creating Capabilities: The Human Development Approach. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.
Okasha, Samir. (2013) ‘Biological Altruism.’ In The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Available from: https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/altruism-biological/
Paine, Thomas. (1973) Originally published in 1791. The Rights of Man. New York: Anchor Books.
Phillips, Anne. (2004) ‘Defending Equality of Outcome.’ LSE Research Online – Journal of Political Philosophy. Vol. 12. No. 1.
             Rawls, John. (1971) A Theory of Justice. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.
Robinson, Nathan J. (2018) ‘Socialism as a Set of Principles.’ In Current Affairs. Available from: https://www.currentaffairs.org/2018/03/socialism-as-a-set-of-principles
Romney, Jonathan. (2011) ‘Krzysztof Kieslowski – Interview for Three Colours Blue.’ In The Guardian. Available from: https://www.theguardian.com/film/2011/nov/09/three-colours-blue-interview
Rude, George. (1964). Revolutionary Europe: 1783-1815. London: Fontana Press.
            Schwartz, James. (1973) ‘Towards Complete Equality? Soviet Views on the Future of Inequality.’ In International Review of Modern Sociology. Vol. 3., No. 2.
Scruton, Roger. (2009) ‘Lesek Kolakowski: Thinker for our Times.’ In Open Democracy. Available from: https://www.opendemocracy.net/en/leszek-kolakowski-thinker-for-our-time-0/
Sloman, Peter. (2011) ‘The Liberal Party and Economic Policy: 1918-1964.’ Open Edition. Available from:  https://journals.openedition.org/mimmoc/695 
            Steele, Jonathan. (2007). ‘Boris Yeltsin.’ In The Guardian. Available from: https://www.theguardian.com/world/2007/apr/23/russia.guardianobituaries

No comments: